Monday, March 11, 2024

Objects Once But No Longer In Use

Greek Culture in South Italy
Krater
370-360 BC
glazed terracotta
Cleveland Museum of Art, Ohio

Roman Empire
Unguentarium
1st-2nd century AD
blown glass
Princeton University Art Museum

Anonymous Dutch Maker
Goblet (Façon de Venise)
17th century
blown glass
Chrysler Museum of Art, Norfolk, Virginia

Johann Paul Schor (designer)
Side Table
ca. 1670
carved, gessoed and gilt poplar, made in Rome
Getty Museum, Los Angeles

Jacob van der Kool
Jar
ca. 1695-1700
faience
Rijksmuseum, Amsterdam

Anonymous Chinese Maker
Vase
18th century
cameo glass
Chrysler Museum of Art, Norfolk, Virginia

Vanessa Bell for Omega Workshops
Plate
ca. 1915
glazed earthenware
Milwaukee Art Museum

Marcel Breuer
Lattenstuhl
1923
oak, cotton, iron
Milwaukee Art Museum

Émile-Antoine Bourdelle
Door Knocker (Head of Medusa)
1925
bronze
Minneapolis Institute of Art

Ruth Asawa
Untitled
1946
copper
Milwaukee Art Museum

Christian Dior
Pin
1950
metal (costume jewelry)
Indianapolis Museum of Art

Bernard Leach
Vase
ca. 1962
earthenware
Milwaukee Art Museum

Elsa Peretti
Covered Tureen
ca. 1986-90
silver
Cleveland Museum of Art

Warren MacKenzie
Platter
ca. 1991
glazed ceramic
Minneapolis Institute of Art

Philippe Starck
Walla-Walla Wall Sconce
1993
molded plastic
Art Institute of Chicago

Katō Tsubusa
Low-sided Vessel
2002
porcelain
Minneapolis Institute of Art

"Why cannot we simply ignore the intended use of an object and judge whether its form is beautiful in complete independence from its utility? And why should our distress at disutility be so great as to block any other pleasure we might take in an object? The answer to this question, at least for Kant and most other eighteenth-century thinkers, is simply that the human mind is inherently teleological – that is, it is natural for us to seek purposes and to find them wherever we can, and to be frustrated when we cannot find them where we think we should be able to do so but to be gratified when we do, and all the more gratified when we succeed in finding purposes where we would have thought we couldn't. In fact, we are particularly frustrated when we fail to find purposiveness where we expect to, although not noticeably pleased when we do find it where we expect to, while when we find it where we do not expect to, we are noticeably pleased, although when we do not find it where we do not expect to find it, we are not noticeably displeased. This set of assumptions would explain the relationship that we find between the perception of utility and of beauty: where we judge the object is ill-adapted to its intended use, our frustration at that is so great as to block other potential pleasures in the object, such as pleasure in the beauty of its form; but where an object is well-adapted to its intended use or other purpose, we pretty much take that for granted, and need an additional element such as beauty of form to take an especially noticeable pleasure in it.  . . .  In other words, the suitability of an object's appearance to its intended use is a necessary condition for our finding the object beautiful, even if finding it beautiful is not reducible to finding its form suitable to its use. Beauty is not identical to utility, but where an object should have utility, then its utility is a necessary condition for its beauty."

– Paul Guyer, Beauty and Utility in Eighteenth-Century Aesthetics (Eighteenth-Century Studies, vol. 35, no. 3, Spring 2002)

Acheulean Culture (Paleolithic France)
Bifaced Hand Axes 
700,000-200,000 BC
flint or quartzite
Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York